Burn Math Class
... when you look at a page full of equations and think "Ahh!
That's scary!", all you're really looking at is a bunch of
simple ideas in a highly abbreviated form. This is true for
every part of mathematics: deconstructing the abbreviations is
more than half the battle.
A sizable proportion of textbooks and lectures just say that
a function is "a rule that assigns one number to another number,"
... For some (including myself when I was first exposed to
the idea), this is a rather confusing conceptual leap.
The first letter of the word "something" in Arabic makes a sound
similar to the sound "sh" in English. It turns out that the
Spanish language has no "sh" sound, so when all of this Arabic
mathematics was translated into Spanish, the Spanish translators
chose the closest thing they could think of. This was the Greek
letter "chi" ... The letter chi looks like this:
χ
... Later as
you might expect this χ
turned into the familiar letter
x from the Latin alphabet.
... when I'm explaining some piece of mathematics to someone, and
I change abbreviations so that we can remember what we're talking
about, one of the most common things I hear is "Oh! I didn't know
we could do that!" It's important that we practice changing
abbreviations, because a lot of ideas in mathematics look scary
and complicated when we use one set of abbreviations, but
suddenly seem obvious when we use another.
We will use
☰
in any equality that is true simply
because of some abbreviation that we're using, and not because of
any mathematics that you missed.
Another way of using equals shows up whenever we're forcing
something to be true, and seeing what happens as a result.
What I cannot create, I do not understand.
- Richard Feynman
- Richard Feynman
The process of inventing a mathematical concept consists of
attempting to translate [a] vague qualitative idea into a
precise quantitative one ... Creation is simply translation
from qualitative to quantitative.
The goal should be, not to implant in the student's mind every
fact that the teacher knows now; but rather to implant a
way of thinking that will enable the student, in the future,
to learn in one year what the teacher learned in two years. ...
As I came to realize this, my style in teaching changed from
giving a smattering of dozens of isolated details, to analyzing
only a few problems, but in some real depth.
- E. T. Jaynes
- E. T. Jaynes
Mathematics is an entire world where nothing is accidental, and
where the mind can train itself with an intensity and precision
unmatched by any other subject.
Mathematics is about sentences that look like: "If this is
true, then that is true."
... you should not try to memorize the steps [of an] argument,
but rather to understand the argument well enough that if you
ever forget [the resulting formulas] (which you should),
then you can reinvent them for yourself on the spot in a few seconds.
New contexts act like a sieve that filters out the possibility
of memorization.
I know it might seem weird to solve a harder problem by using a
simpler method, but this strategy turns out to work all over the
place in mathematics. It's really fortunate that things work out
that way!
... the fact that multiplication works the same both ways (i.e.
a*b = b*a) just says that the area of a rectangle doesn't change
when we turn it on its side.
... our choice of a formal definition often depends (more than
anyone wants to admit) on subjective aesthetic preferences, i.e.,
what we think is pretty.
A steep thing is equally steep whether we climb it when we're
underground or when we're inside an airplane.
The essence of mathematics lies entirely in its freedom.
- Georg Cantor
- Georg Cantor
As is always the case when inventing a mathematical concept, the
definition we finally arrived at was built from a strange blend
of translation and aesthetics: some of our definition's behaviors
came from our desire to make it behave like our everyday concept,
while other came from a desire to make the resulting definition
as elegant and simple to deal with as possible...
Textbooks call abbreviations "symbols," and they call sentences
"equations" or "formulas."
... for decades we've been teaching students everything they need
to understand [time dilation], and then simply not bothering
to show it to them. Why? Because special relativity is an
"advanced" topic that doesn't quite "belong" in an introductory
physics class, nor does it seem to belong in the courses on
Euclidean geometry in which students first learn the mathematics
needed to understand the argument itself. The argument is homeless.
... a surprising amount of knowledge can be squeezed out of the
simple fact that drawing a picture on something doesn't change
its area.
If two things really are equal (i.e. identical), and we
modify both in exactly the same way, then (although the two things
will both change individually) they will still be identical
to each other after the modifications ... identical modifications
to identical objects must lead to identical results.
Here's the seemingly impossible fact about light: if you "throw" some
light ... and then you immediately run up behind it at 99% of the
speed of light, then it won't look like the light is moving
away from you at 1% of the speed of light! Rather, it will still look
like the light is moving away from you at the full speed of light...
... people usually use the letter c to stand for the speed
of light. Basically, c is the first letter of the Latin
word for "swiftness," and the speed of light is quite literally the
fastest anything in our universe is able to go...
Calculus is the most powerful weapon of thought yet devised by
the wit of man.
- W. B. Smith
- W. B. Smith
By stumbling upon a familiar location, you've managed to reduce
the problem to one you've already solved in the past, and the
rest is easy. That's all of mathematics!
All of Calculus: If we zoom in on curvy stuff, it starts to look
more and more straight ... What's more, if we were to zoom in
"infinitely far" (whatever that means), then any curvy thing
would look exactly straight.
... if we can invent an "infinite magnifying glass" -- then we'll
be able to turn any problem involving curvy stuff (a hard problem)
into a problem involving straight stuff (an easy problem).
If we forget about mathematics and just stare at a curvy thing ...
it's very clear that some places are more steep than others ...
Is there any way to make sense of the idea of steepness at a
single point of some general curvy thing?
What does it mean for two points to be infinitely close to each
other?
To this day calculus all over the world is being taught as a
study of limit processes instead of what it really is:
infinitesimal analysis.
- Rudy Rucker
- Rudy Rucker
If the idea of infinitely small numbers scares you a little,
you're not alone! ... How can we act like it's not zero, and then
a few lines later act like it is zero?
One of the contraptions that can be used to formalize the idea of
infinitely small numbers is called an "ultrafilter." Ultrafilters
are pretty complicated and never mentioned in the introductory textbooks.
... the contraption you'll see in all the standard intro textbooks
is called a "limit," ... it lets mathematicians get all the
benefits of using infinitely small numbers, without
giving the idea of infinitely small numbers any of the credit.
It's less confusing if we realize that limits are just one of
several (optional!) contraptions that let us avoid worrying about
the meaning of infinitely small numbers if we want to.
... to change an expression involving regular numbers to an expression
involving infinitely small ones, just change the Greek alphabet to
the Latin alphabet (i.e., change
Δ
to d) ...
Similarly, we'll see later that when the textbooks pass from the letter
Σ
(the Greek S, which stands for the word "sum")
to its corresponding Latin letter S (they actually write
∫
, which kind of looks like an S), they're
doing a similar trick. ... we'll soon see how switching back and
forth between different abbreviations has a surprising ability to
make complicated things seem simple ...
Since a machine's derivative tells us the slope of the machine at that
point, we can make use of the following convenient fact: all flat
points of a machine are places where that machine's derivate is zero.
As such, we can find the flat points of a machine m by
forcing its derivative to be zero ... and then trying to figure
out which numbers x make that sentence true.
Not all the flat points are extremes, but both of the extremes are
flat points.
If we're at a max or min, then the derivative is zero
... the basic principle that "extremes are usually places where the
derivative equals zero" will continue to apply no matter how far
we go, and no matter how strange our mathematical universe becomes.
... the ultra-cautious "how do I know if I'm right?" feeling we all
develop in mathematics classes is a feeling that we should, at least
partially, learn to abandon. When we're inventing mathematics (or
anything) for ourselves, we don't know if we're right.
No one ever does.
The old saying among physicists appears to be true: too much rigor
can, and does, lead to rigor mortis.
... the notation
dM/dx
, which emphasizes that the
derivative of M can be thought of as the "rise over run"
between two points that are infinitely close to each other.
... you'll occasionally hear people talking about strange things
like "negative powers" or "fractional powers" or "zeroth powers" ...
.... how should we chooe to generalize the concept of powers?
Obviously, any generalization is useless unless it is useful.
I have no idea what (stuff)# means when # isn't a whole number...
But I really want to hold on to the sentence:
(stuff)n+m = (stuff)n(stuff)m
So I'll force (stuff)# to mean: whatever it has to mean in order to make that sentence keep being true.
(stuff)n+m = (stuff)n(stuff)m
So I'll force (stuff)# to mean: whatever it has to mean in order to make that sentence keep being true.
This style of thought lies at the core of mathematical invention, and
a surprising number of mathematical concepts are invented in exactly
this way.
... (stuff)0 has to be whatever number doesn't change things
when you multiply by it. So I guess (stuff)0 has to be 1.
1 = (stuff)0 = (stuff)#(stuff)-#
(stuff)-# = 1/(stuff)#
(stuff)-# = 1/(stuff)#
(stuff)1/n is any number that can say the following sentence
without lying: "Multiply me by myself n times and you get
(stuff)."
We have a habit in writing articles published in scientific journals
to make the work as finished as possible, to cover all the tracks,
to not worry about the blind alleys or to describe how you had
the wrong idea first, and so on. So there isn't any place to publish,
in a dignified manner, what you actually did in order to get to
do the work...
- Richard Feynman
- Richard Feynman
If M(x)
then M'(x) = f'(x)g(x) + f(x)g'(x)
☰
f(x)g(x)then M'(x) = f'(x)g(x) + f(x)g'(x)
What if we made an argument, in abbreviated form, that whenever
we know the pattern is true for one number of machines multiplied
together, then it has to be true for the next number? Then we
would automatically know that the pattern was true for every number.
... Textbooks call this style of reasoning "mathematical induction."
... Despite all [the] unrelated meanings of induction, if you
hear it used after the word "mathematical," then they're talking
about this ladder-like process of reasoning.